Year
after year, we confront, we explain. Maybe we get minor concessions. Then
presto, something happens, and even those handouts are gone. (S. R., activist and interviewee)
On several occasions I have written about
the complexities of antipsychiatry politics, exploring more specifically, how
to “do our politics” in a way that moves society squarely in the direction of the
abolitionist goal (e.g., Burstow, 2014). In this article, I am once again
theorizing the “how” of activism—for understanding this territory is critical to
maximizing effectiveness. However, this time round, I am approaching it from an
angle at once more general and more practical. That is, I am investigating the
tools or approaches at our disposal as activists. What relates to this, I will be
discussing the genus of politic—that is, the manner of politics being engaged.
Pivotal questions grappled with in this
article include: What fundamental approaches might be taken to end/rein in
psychiatry? What are the strengths and shortcomings of each? What dangers do
they present? To what larger genus of politic do they belong? How are we to understand these in themselves?
In relation to psychiatry? What are some of the enigmas, or challenges facing
us? And how might they be met?
Now obviously, very different approaches
might be adopted depending on the intended target of our change efforts—psychiatrists,
survivors whom we hope to influence, our selves, the general public, the state.
For the purpose of this article, I will largely be limiting the focal target to
those with power in this area on one hand and the general public on the other.
That said, let me suggest that there are
two overarching or umbrella approaches available to us as activists—persuasion
on one hand and the application of political pressure on the other (for an articulation
of these principles in relation a neighbouring movement, see Rosenthal, 1996).
To begin with persuasion, persuasion is
predicated on the supposition that if we make our points well enough, say, by assembling
cogent evidence, by making it assessable, by personalizing this with
sensitizing stories and other emotional persuaders, people will become
convinced that action of the type suggested is called for—for example, that ECT
should be abolished. Correspondingly, it is assumed that there is an extremely
close relationship between people being persuaded and change happening. Now
whatever the limitation of this perspective and this approach, without question,
persuasion is a key element in most change processes. Moreover, it is part of
our existential nature to try to persuade and to move. Understandably, correspondingly,
efforts at persuasion abound in our movement, whether we call what we are doing
providing information, exposing, sensitizing, telling our story, or educating. Examples
are: almost all the articles in Mad in America, the books that we pen, fact
sheets that we produce, dialogues that we invite.
That said, I would agree that this is a
necessary, even pivotal dimension. Why, for example, would the public support
banning ECT short of becoming convinced that it is inherently damaging? Our
tools here—and it is important to master them—include: sound scientific
evidence, latest findings, cogent analysis, people’s stories, with ones with
which public can identify being particular important, for they heighten
empathy, lead to “aha” movements, and motivate. And with all of this,
painstaking accuracy is critical. Note, the establishment can get away with
lying, twisting, and exaggerating—we cannot.
That granted, a number of questions arise.
First, are there risks involved in heavily relying on persuasion? Let me
suggest that indeed, there are, with the risks different for different types of
persuasion. To begin with the simplest of these, when trying to persuade, especially
when using personal stories as persuaders, we can readily fall into what has
been called “the politics of compassion” (in the politics of compassion, we are
in essence leveraging the compassion that people feel or can be induced to feel
to effect the changes sought; for an articulation of this concept, see
Rosenthal, 1996). To be clear, I am in no way trying to minimize the importance
of compassion. Nonetheless, the politics of compassion is at best a tenuous
base from which to proceed. Why? For one, the presence of compassion does not in
and of itself mean that the shift that materializes will be benign, despite our
best efforts. In this regard, strange though this may seem, most people who
support forced drugging are convinced that there are thereby being
compassionate to the objects of the force. Additionally, even good changes made
on such a basis tend to be less than reliable. Why? Because people whose
political decisions stem overwhelmingly from compassion seldom have a solid
grasp of the territory. Correspondingly, the object of their compassion can
shift—and as a result, such changes can be very short-lived.
One way that this happens is by the
establishment likewise appealing to compassion. In this regard, in the early 1980s
ECT survivors frequently got on tv and moved the public with chilling stories
of how the treatment ruined their lives—seemingly, real progress. Within short
order, though, psychiatrists were bringing their own patients onto shows with
them, with the patients testifying how ECT had saved their lives. The audience was still compassionate but
compassion now culminated in support for the status quo.
Indeed, even when substantial (and benign) changes
have materialized, in the absence of a more solid base, they can quickly be
reversed. Consider, in this regard, the great strides made with respect to psychiatric
survivor rights in the 1980s. In Ontario Canada, for instance, education on the
impossible plight of psychiatric survivors led to legal changes predicated on
the notion that the default mode should be survivors making their own decisions.
Shortly thereafter, however, a man called Brian was killed by someone identified
as “disordered” and the incident was seized
upon by institutional psychiatry, its supporters, and the media. Whereupon, the
public’s compassion shifted from survivors per se to what was seen as their potential
victims. The result was the passing of Brian’s Law—a piece of legislation which
dramatically lowered the bar on what suffices to incarcerate involuntarily (for
details, see Burstow, 2015a).
For changes to be benign, solid, and
enduring, in other words, additional education is needed that goes beyond the
education typically associated with the politics of compassion. Examples are: education
debunking the myth of the dangerous mental patient, education around the
inefficacy of and the harm done by the “treatments,” and education on psychiatry’s
lack of foundation. More fundamentally, if substantial and enduring change is
to be achieved, the politics of entitlement has to take precedence over the
politics of compassion. To hone in on consent, for example, the message that
needs to be delivered is: Irrespective of how others may feel, it is everyone’s
right to be free.
This being the case, public education on people’s
rights is important. And of particular importance are initiatives like Tina
Minkowitz’s, which culminated in the U.N. declaring involuntary treatment
torture (see Minkowitz, 2014). And here we move from liberal to radical
education, and, indeed, consciousness-raising.
At this point the question arises: If
education is both more thorough and more radical, will it then suffice? At risk
of frustrating the reader, let me suggest, for the most part, no. And here, we
come up against the limitations of persuasion, also the inadequacy of what
passes as common sense. In this regard, it is commonly believed that if
provided with good evidence and ways to relate, people can be persuaded to see
things differently; correspondingly, once enough
people or the right people are so
persuaded, social change, ipso facto, will occur. The very fact that for
decades now an abundance of scholars,
activists, and survivors have masterfully provided such education (e.g., Szasz,
Breggin, Frank) and yet psychiatry continues to command respect and to grow is
itself an indicator that such an understanding is too simplistic. While of
course, on some level or other, persuasion is generally at work when change
happens, what such a perspective ignores is the very fact of power and how it
works.
The point is that there are structures and there
is a profession here endowed with authority. And there are huge vested
interests at play—the multinational pharmaceutical companies, for example,
armies of “professional helpers”, indeed
the entire psychiatric/psychopharmaceutical industrial complex. These yield enormous
power, including the power to determine who
and what is credible. Correspondingly,
they can be counted on to use that power to further their own interests, including
their own bottom line. On top of which the public is wary of people whom they
see as mad— and so want such structures in place. Moreover, the industry has
vast sums of money and other capital at their disposal, and whenever it has
seen public sentiment shift against it, it has invariably responded by drawing
on its extensive resources to wage a new campaign (for details, see Burstow,
2015a). All formidable reasons why persuasion does not suffice.
If the combination of logic, facticity, and
fellow feeling, while essential, do not suffice—and I am suggesting that they
do not—what else is needed? At this point in history at any rate, force. The
point is, insofar as an oppressor wields power, and insofar as we are trying to
overturn a system that is inherently oppressive and all-encompassing, we too
need to wield power. To be clear, I am in no way suggesting physical force, but
non-violent action such as that waged by visionaries like Gandhi (see Sharp,
1973).
Now indeed, albeit it is underutilized, to
varying degrees nonviolent resistance too has always figured in our repertoire.
Note, in this regard, the Highlander work, wherein survivors pointedly modeled themselves on the civil
rights movement. Note the demonstrations in the UK (see Mckeown, Creswell, and
Spandler, 2014). Correspondingly, witness MindFreedom’s 2002 hunger strike (for
details, see http://www.mindfreedom.org/kb/act/2003/mf-hunger-strike/hunger-strike-news?searchterm=hunger+
).
The latter, I would add, is a particularly
instructive action to probe. The protestors’ ultimate demand was the provision
of choice in “services”; and in the process of making this demand, they challenged
the American Psychiatric Association and the National Institute of Mental
Health to point to a single study showing that “mental illness” is
biological—which, of course, they could not. This action was nothing short of
remarkable; it included among its team no less a figure than the former head of
“schizophrenia studies” at National Institute of Mental Health; it brought
together survivors and radical professionals, drawing on the knowledge of each;
it garnered press; it brought goals, methods, and means of measurement into
alignment with each other, as is critical in strategic activism; correspondingly,
it constituted a formidable education in its own right. At the same time, even
this stellar piece of activism fell short of achieving its objective. Nor did
it exactly create a base from which to proceed. And here is the rub.
Now to be clear, as I have stated elsewhere
(Burstow, 2015b), standing up and being counted is important irrespective of effectiveness. And so is
raising awareness even when nothing concrete
materializes. Nonetheless, insofar as our goal is social change, effectiveness in
the strictest sense of the term matters. So the question is: what kind of pressure
can we bring to bear that might actually materialize in change? In short, there
are two types of pressure involved in non-violent action. The first is moral
force, also known as the force of truth (and the personal stories alluded to
earlier are a part of this). Such is arguably achievable in our movement, for
the cause is just and the harm demonstrable.
That said, while moral force is absolutely
critical—and for sure it was being wielded in that hunger strike—it similarly does
not suffice. In this regard, history teaches us—and we ignore this to our
peril—that moral pressure needs to be combined with pressure of a more material
kind. Note, in India when Gandhi mobilized against the British colonizers, or
to add a second example, when the Black community in Nashville sought to
desegregate the commercial centre of their city, they were successful because
not only had they moral force, they used and leveraged the power of numbers to
obstruct. In this regard, the oppressed inhabitants of India greatly outnumbered
the British occupiers, did all the work utilized by the regime, and so by the
very act of striking, they were able to bring production to a halt and in the
process, undermine the British. By the same token, the Black community in
Nashville was sufficiently large that once the overwhelming majority of Black
residents (plus allies) had joined the ongoing boycott of stores practicing
segregation (more or less all stores in central Nashville) and had engaged in
it long enough, the seemingly intransigent merchants of Nashville were, in
essence, brought to their knees (for a blow-by-blow of this very extensive
campaign, see York, 2000).
To put this simply,
the question facing any movement intent
on change is leverage. Having large enough numbers that you can stop the work of
industry constitutes leverage. Being able to wield sufficient economic power that
simply by refusing to purchase you can materially affect companies’ bottom line
constitutes leverage. Now generally, the leverage in question is of an economic
nature, but there is no obvious reason why this must be so. That noted, the
question facing our movement is this: Besides the morality of our cause, exactly what is our leverage? And if we
haven’t sufficient leverage now—which I am suggesting is the case—what kind of
leverage can we get and how do we acquire more?
The answer to this question is anything but
obvious. A course which I teach (Creative Empowerment Work with the
Disenfanchized) is instructive in this regard. Year after year, I have engaged
students in an exercise—and it invariably ends with the same impasse: The class
having been divided into three, each group is tasked with brainstorming a
strategic piece of resistance that would stand a reasonable chance of being
successful—group one, in regard to homelessness, group two with respect to prisons,
group three with regards to psychiatry. While all three encounter difficulties,
almost invariably, it is the students in the antipsychiatry group that flounder.
Why? Precisely because, try though they might, they cannot locate a point of
leverage.
This said, arguably, the single biggest task
confronting us as a movement is finding or generating leverage. Boycotting the
drugs, clearly, would not get the unity needed and would otherwise backfire. And
in the end, even at its best, the only pressure of use to us that would arise from
a hunger strike is moral pressure, which short of having a person with the
reputation of Gandhi at the helm, is not going to advance the movement far.
I do not have a clear answer to the dilemma
posed here, though I can hazard some guesses about direction. Insofar as lack
of numbers presents a formidable obstacle to any strategy, let me suggest that
coalition politics appears to be called for. Note, if even a modest percentage
of the people poorly served by society banded together, we would greatly
outnumber the establishment, and as such, arguably, the necessary critical mass
could be forged. Though to accomplish this, obviously, ongoing work reaching
out and co-visioning would be critical.
Not an easy or a quick answer, I agree, but
one with the added advantage of being holistic and truly leading in the
direction of a better society.
In summation, there are very serviceable
tools at our disposal as antipsychiatry activists—and these include various
kinds of persuasion and force. Correspondingly, it is critical that we know
them, select and use them skillfully. At the same time, major challenges
confront us. Getting past our conviction
that persuasion suffices is one of them—and then there are the material
problems, together with issues like power and leverage. Hopefully, this article
has shed a little more clarity on all of such aspects. And hopefully, the
reflections and dialogue started here can continue.
Indeed, as you go about your work, I invite
the reader to continue pondering the distinctions, queries, and challenges raised.
In particular, I invite you to ask yourself: What power do we wield? Could we
wield? Who historically have our allies been? (e.g., homelessness activists,
prison abolitionists, Quakers) And who might new allies be? As an addendum, correspondingly,
I leave you with the following consideration:
No campaign is successful without images. And
if chosen judiciously, symbols can be of considerable help in generating
leverage.
One possibility in this regard is using the
violence of ECT as a symbol for psychiatry overall (see Burstow, 2015b). What
might be at least as potent—and I think that we would do well to seriously
entertain this possibility—is to focus in on the psychiatrization of children.
By this I do not mean what happened to current adult survivors when young (important
though this dimension is), but the rampant targeting of children going on now (see
Whitaker, 2010). Children being placed on Ritalin. Children being labeled ADHD.
Children being controlled/subdued chemically in classrooms around the world. Herein
lies a powerful symbol. Question: If we leverage it properly, might not the
public at large be moved to rally in protection of its children? And were that
possible, in the long run, might not such a focus deliver the numbers needed
for strategic action?
What is significant here, irrespective of espoused
belief, understandably (given that the young in particular are entrusted to our
care), people are readily outraged by what happens to children, and more
pointedly, what happens or could happen to their
child. And significantly, the vast majority of the human population are
parents, grandparents, and the like. Now for sure, a frightening number of
parents, moreover, the vast majority of ones publicly weighing on these issues are
in the opposite camp, have become, in essence, an extension of psychiatry. By
the same token, a particularly formidable weapon in psychiatry’s current arsenal
are pro-medical model family organizations like NAMI, tutored, funded, and
otherwise resourced by the psychopharmaceuticals. This notwithstanding, those
of us who organize in this area have witnessed first hand the enormous power
that can be unleashed when parents suddenly realize that they have been, as it
were, “sold a bill of goods”. As such, arguably, if we put our minds to
reaching and leveraging the power of this very considerable constituency (of
which we, after all, are a part), for the first time in history, we might be
able to create the leverage needed—indeed, potentially, leverage beyond our
wildest dreams—a good beginning.
Insofar as this is the case, I would add,
the greed of the psychiatric/psychopharmaceutical industry in relentlessly
pursuing this erstwhile “untapped market”—the real reason that our children
have been targeted—could prove to be its own undoing.
References
Burstow, B. (2014). The withering of psychiatry: An attrition model
for antipsychiatry. In B. Burstow, B. LeFrançois, & S. Diamond (Eds.), Psychiatry disrupted: Theorizing resistance
and crafting the revolution (pp. 34-51).
Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press.
Burstow, B. (2015a). Psychiatry
and the business of madness: An ethical and epistemological accounting. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Burstow, B. (2015b). Protesting ECT. Retrieved on April 3 2015 from http://www.madinamerica.com/2015/03/protesting-ect-moralexistential-calling/.
Mckeown, M., Creswell, M., and Spandler, H. (2014). Deeply engaged
relationships. In B. Burstow, B. LeFrançois, & S. Diamond (Eds.), Psychiatry disrupted: Theorizing resistance
and crafting the revolution (pp. 145-162). Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press.
Minkowitz, T. (2014). Convention on the rights of persons with disabilities
and liberation from psychiatric oppression. In B. Burstow, B. LeFrançois, &
S. Diamond (Eds.), Psychiatry disrupted:
Theorizing resistance and crafting the revolution (pp. 129-144). Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University
Press.
Rosenthal, R. (1996). Dilemmas of local antihomelessness movements.
In J. Baumohl (Ed.). Homelessness in
America (pp. 201-232). Phoenix, Arizona: Oryx Press.
Sharp, G. (1973). The politics
of nonviolent action. Boston: Porter Sargent Publications.
Whitaker, R. (2010). Anatomy
of an epidemic. New York: Broadway Paperbacks.
York, S. (2000). A force more powerful (PBS). New York: United
States Institute of Peace.
The number one failed strategy this year in the 'movement', is this mindless assumption that society will ever ban voluntary ECT. Yes, many people regret ECT. Yes, it's a ridiculous electric shock pseudoscience and not a real 'treatment' for anything. Yes, like many voluntary acts at causes harm, like smoking does. But you're dreaming if you think that hundreds of thousands of people who consented to it and identify as finding it helpful, are going to tolerate their freedom to fry their brains being taken away. This kind of totalitarian impulse, banning consensual, voluntary psychiatry, is totally misguided, focus on forced psychiatry. Society can see the clear violence and terror of forced psychiatry. It's disappointing that anyone in this movement thinks that a total 'ban' on voluntary shock, is ever going to fly. It's not.
ReplyDeleteDoctors minimally should not be administering procedures as if they are medical treatments when they are not. And ECT, in this regard ,qualifies, for no credible medical claim can be made for it. Note also that mostly (albeit not totally) lobotomy was stopped albeit there were people who swore that it helped them. The point is, no a total ban on doctors offering ECT is not impossible, for we have had comparable things happen in the past.
ReplyDeleteIt's not about whether a total ban is "impossible", banning books, certain races, whatever, all sorts of total bans have been politically achieved in human history. It is about whether you have the moral right to deny people a procedure that they want to acquire, in my view, you don't. You're being totalitarian and it is not a good look. Hundreds of thousands of more people swear by electroshock than they did for lobotomy. You stand zero chance of banning it.
DeleteDo you wish to outlaw naturopathy? chiropractic? all sorts of quack "treatments" that involve adding things to the body or manipulating the body but are also not "medical" in the sense of mainstream evidence based modern medicine? Or are you prepared to allow them the freedom to exist? Would a number of people claiming their back pain got worse from chiropractic manipulation turn you into a crusader to "totally ban" chiropractic?
I do not support a ban on CONSENSUAL provision and procurement of services between consenting adults. It disappoints me that you do.
Businesses offer laser hair removal and call it a "treatment", you don't, I don't, psychiatry doesn't, the government doesn't, have a monopoly on the word "treatment". If someone wants to pay to get electric shocks through their brain, or pay to get ink injected into their skin in the form of a tattoo, a cohort of regretters, does not justify a total ban on consensual services.
It is totalitarian to want to use the state to make it a crime for the electroshock CONSENSUAL seekers and providers to engage in what to them is a mutually beneficial relationship.
The "day of protest" (at other people's consensual freedom to buy and acquire electroshock), remains the most embarrassing strategic mistake of 2015 for this movement. It's embarrassing.
Next you'll be saying the psychiatric drugs should be "total banned" for the same rationale.
It's not just disappointing that you think a ban could every fly, it's disappointing that you think you have the right to tell people what they can and can't seek out as an option. Very disappointing.
Let me suggest that there is a fundamental logical inherent in looking at all things that call themselves "treatments" as is a natural right that not offering them means a deprivation of freedom. We pay doctors to offer certain services to the public under the understanding that they do indeed serve. If it can shown that anything is a disservice, doctors simply should not be offering it. In this regard, that is different than interfering with what people under their own initiative do to themselves.
ReplyDelete(Repetition of above with missing word inserted)
ReplyDeleteLet me suggest that there is a fundamental logical fallacy inherent in looking at all things that call themselves "treatments" as is a natural right that not offering them means a deprivation of freedom. We pay doctors to offer certain services to the public under the understanding that they do indeed serve. If it can shown that anything is a disservice, doctors simply should not be offering it. In this regard, that is different than interfering with what people under their own initiative do to themselves.